صور الصفحة
PDF
النشر الإلكتروني

such it would actually be, whatever were the provision of the law-whether, for instance, confiscation of property, or indignity to the remains of the dead. One would make a family poor, and the other perhaps unhappy. It does not appear just or reasonable that these should suffer for an offence which they could not prevent, and by which they, above all others, are already injured and distressed.

One thing appears to be clear, that it is vain for a Legislature to attempt any interference of which the people do not approve. This is evident from the experience in our own country, where coroner's juries prefer perjuring themselves to pronouncing a verdict of felo de se, by which the remains would be subjected to barbarous indignities. Coroners' inquests seem to proceed rather upon the pre-supposition that he who destroys himself is insane, than upon the evidence which is brought before them; and thus, whilst the law is evaded, perjury it is to be feared is very frequent. That the public mind disapproves the existing law is a good reason for altering it but it is not a good reason why coroners' juries should violate their oaths, and give encouragement to the suicide by telling him, that disgrace will be warded off from his memory and from his family by a generous verdict of insanity. It has been said that it is a common thing for a suicide's friends to fee the coroner in order to induce him to prevent a verdict of felo de se. If this be true, it is indeed time that the arm of the law should be vigorously extended. What punishment is due to the man who accepts a purse as a reward for inducing twelve persons to commit perjury? It is probable too, that half-a-dozen just verdicts, by which the law was allowed to take its course, would occasion the abolition of the disgusting statute; for the public would not bear that it should be acted upon.

The great object is to associate with the act of suicide ideas of guilt and horror in the public mind. This association would be likely to preclude, in individuals, that first complacent contemplation of the act which probably precedes, by a long interval, the act itself. The anxiety which the surviving friends manifest for a verdict of "insanity," is a proof how great is the power of imagination, and how much they are in dread of public opinion. They are anxious that the disgrace and reproach of conscious self-murder should not cling to their family. This is precisely that anxiety of which the legislator should avail himself, by enactments that would require satisfactory proof of insanity, and which, in default of such proof, would leave to its full force the stigma and the pain, and excite a sense of horror of the act, and a perception of its wickedness in the public mind. The point for the exercise of legislative wisdom is, to devise such an ultimate procedure as shall call forth these feelings, but as shall not become nugatory by being more dreadful than the public will endure. What that procedure should be, I pretend not to describe; but it may be observed that the simple circumstance of pronouncing a public verdict of conscious self-murder, would, amongst a people of good feelings, go far towards the production of the desired effect.-As the law now exists, and as it is now violated, the tendency is exactly the contrary of what it ought to be. By the almost universal custom which it generates, of declaring suicides to have been insane, it effectually diminishes that pain to individuals, and that horror in the public, which the crime itself would naturally occasion.

• This statute has been repealed; and the law now simply requires, when a verdict of felo de se is returned, that the body shall be interred privately, at night, and without the funeral service. Ed.

CHAPTER XVII.

RIGHTS OF SELF-DEFENCE.

These rights not absolute-Their limits-Personal attackPreservation of property-Much resistance lawful-Effects of forbearance-Sharpe-Barclay-Ellwood.

THE right of defending ourselves against violence is easily deducible from the Law of Nature. There is however little need to deduce it, because mankind are at least sufficiently persuaded of its lawfulness. -The great question, which the opinions and principles that now influence the world makes it needful to discuss is, Whether the right of self-defence is absolute and unconditional-Whether every action whatever is lawful, provided it is necessary to the preservation of life? They who maintain the affirmative, maintain a great deal; for they maintain that whenever life is endangered, all rules of morality are, as it respects the individual, suspended, annihilated: : every moral obligation is taken away by the single fact that life is threatened.

Yet the language that is ordinarily held upon the "If our subject implies the supposition of all this. lives are threatened with assassination or open violence from the hands of robbers or enemies, any means of defence would be allowed, and laudable."* Again, "There is one case in which all extremities are justifiable, namely, when our life is assaulted, and it becomes necessary for our preservation to kill the assailant."+

The reader may the more willingly enquire whether these propositions are true, because most of those who lay them down are at little pains to prove their truth. Men are extremely willing to acquiesce in it without proof, and writers and speakers think it unnecessary to adduce it. Thus perhaps it happens that fallacy is not detected because it is not sought. If the reader should think that some of

the instances which follow are remote from the ordinary affairs of life, he is requested to remember that we are discussing the soundness of an alleged absolute rule. If it be found that there are or have been cases in which it is not absolute-cases in which all extremities are not lawful in defence of lifethen the rule is not sound: then there are some limits to the Right of Self-Defence.

If he may,

If "any means of defence are laudable," if "all extremities are justifiable," then they are not confined to acts of resistance to the assailing party. There may be other conditions upon which life may be preserved than that of violence towards him. Some ruffians seize a man in the highway, and will kill him unless he will conduct them to his neighbour's property and assist them in carrying it off. May this man unite with them in the robbery in order to save his life, or may he not? what becomes of the law, Thou shalt not steal? If he may not, then not every means by which a man "allowed." may preserve his life is "laudable" We have found an exception to the rule. There are twenty other wicked things which violent men may make the sole condition of not taking our lives. Do all wicked things become lawful because life is at stake? If they do, Morality is surely at an end: if they do not, such propositions as those of Grotius and Paley are untrue.

or

A pagan has unalterably resolved to offer me up in sacrifice on the morrow, unless I will acknowledge the deity of his gods and worship them. I shall presume that the Christian will regard these acts as being, under every possible circumstance, unlawful. The night offers me an opportunity of assassinating

Grotius: Rights o War and Peace.

Paley Mor. and Pol. Phil. p 3, b. iv. c. 1.

him. Now I am placed, so far as the argument is concerned, in precisely the same situation with respect to this man, as a traveller is with respect to a ruffian with a pistol. Life in both cases depends on killing the offender. Both are acts of self-defence. Am I at liberty to assassinate this man? The heart of the Christian surely answers, No. Here then is a case in which I may not take a violent man's life in order to save my own.-We have said that the heart of the Christian answers, No: and this we think is a just species of appeal. But if any one doubts whether the assassination would be unlawful, let him consider whether one of the Christian apostles would have committed it in such a case. Here, at any rate, the heart of every man answers, No. And mark the reason-because every man perceives that the act would have been palpably inconsistent with apostolic character and conduct; or, which is the same thing, with a Christian character and conduct.

Or put such a case in a somewhat different form. A furious Turk holds a scimitar over my head, and declares he will instantly dispatch me unless I abjure Christianity and acknowledge the divine legation of "the Prophet." Now there are two supposable ways in which I may save my life; one by contriving to stab the Turk, and one "by denying Christ before men." You say I am not at liberty to deny Christ, but I am at liberty to stab the man. Why am I not at liberty to deny Him? Because Christianity forbids it. Then we require you to show that Christianity does not forbid you to take his life. Our religion pronounces both actions to be wrong. You say that, under these circumstances, the killing is right. Where is your proof? What is the ground of your distinction ?-But, whether it can be adduced or not, our immediate argument is established-That there are some things which it is not lawful to do in order to preserve our lives. This conclusion has indeed been practically acted upon. A company of inquisitors and their agents are about to conduct a good man to the stake. If he could by any means destroy these men, he might save his life. It is a question therefore of self defence. Supposing these means to be within his power-supposing he could contrive a mine, and by suddenly firing it, blow his persecutors into the air-would it be lawful and Christian thus to act? No. The common judgments of mankind respecting the right temper and conduct of the martyr, pronounce it to be wrong. nounced to be wrong by the language and example of the first teachers of Christianity. The conclusion therefore again is, that all extremities are not allow. able in order to preserve life;-that there is a limit to the right of self-defence.

It is pro

It would be to no purpose to say that in some of the instances which have been proposed, religious duties interfere with and limit the rights of selfdefence. This is a common fallacy. Religious duties and moral duties are identical in point of obligation, for they are imposed by one authority. Religious duties are not obligatory for any other reason than that which attaches to moral duties also; namely, the Will of God. He who violates the Moral Law is as truly unfaithful in his allegiance to God, as he who denies Christ before men.

So that we come at last to one single and simple question, whether taking the life of a person who threatens ours, is or is not compatible with the Moral Law. We refer for an answer to the broad principles of Christian piety and Christian benevolence; that piety which reposes habitual confidence in the Divine Providence, and an habitual preference of futurity to the present time; and that benevolence which not only loves our neighbours as ourselves, but feels that the Samaritan or the enemy is a neighbour. There is no

conjecture in life in which the exercise of his bene volence may be suspended; none in which we are not required to maintain and to practise it. Whether Want implores our compassion, or Ingratitude returns ills for our kindness; whether a fellow crea ture is drowning in a river or assailing us on the highway; every where, and under all circumstances, the duty remains.

Is killing an assailant, then, within or without the limits of this Benevolence?-As to the man, it is evident that no good-will is exercised towards him by shooting him through the head. Who indeed will dispute that, before we can thus destroy him, benevolence towards him must be excluded from our minds? We not only exercise no benevolence ourselves, but preclude him from receiving it from any human heart; and, which is a serious item in the account, we cut him off from all possibility of reformation. To call sinners to repentance, was one of the great characteristics of the mission of Christ. Does it appear consistent with this characteristic for one of His followers to take away from a sinner the power of repentance? Is it an act that accords, and is congruous, with Christian love?

But an argument has been attempted here. That we may "kill the assailant is evident in a state of nature, unless it can be shown that we are bound to prefer the aggressor's life to our own; that is to say, to love our enemy better than ourselves, which can never be a debt of justice, nor any where appears to be a duty of charity."* The answer is this: That although we may not be required to love our enemy better than ourselves, we are required to love him as ourselves; and therefore, in the supposed case, it would still be a question equally balanced which life ought to be sacrificed; for it is quite clear that, if we kill the assailant, we love him less than ourselves, which does seem to militate against a duty of charity. But the truth is that he who, from motives of obedience to the will of God, spares the aggressor's life even to the endangering his own, does exercise love both to the aggressor and to himself, perfectly: to the aggressor, because by sparing his life we give him the opportunity of repentance and amendment: to himself, because every act of obedience to God is perfect benevolence towards ourselves; it is consulting and promoting our most valuable interests; it is propitiating the favour of him who is emphatically "a rich rewarder."-So that the question remains as before, not whether we should love our enemy better than ourselves, but whether Christian principles are acted upon in destroying him; and if they are not, whether we should prefer Christianity to ourselves; whether we should be willing to lose our life for Christ's sake and the gospel's.

Perhaps it will be said that we should exercise benevolence to the public as well as to the offender, and that we may exercise more benevolence to them by killing than by sparing him. But very few persons, when they kill a man who attacks them, kill him out of benevolence to the public. That is not the motive which influences their conduct, or which they at all take into the account. Besides, it is by no means certain that the public would lose any thing by the forbearance. To be sure, a man can do no more mischief after he is killed; but then it is to be remembered, that robbers are more desperate and more murderous from the apprehension of swords and pistols than they would be without it. Men are desperate in proportion to their apprehensions of danger. The plunderer who feels a confidence that his own life will not be taken, may conduct his plunder with comparative gentleness; whilst he who

• Paley: Mor. and Pol. Phil. p. 3, b. 4, c. 1.

knows that his life is in immediate jeopardy, stuns or | murders his victim lest he should be killed himself. The great evil which a family sustains by a robbery is often not the loss, but the terror and the danger; and these are the evils which, by the exercise of forbearance, would be diminished. So that, if some bad men are prevented from committing robberies by the fear of death, the public gains in other ways by the forbearance: nor is it by any means certain that the balance of advantages is in favour of the more violent course. The argument which we are opposing proceeds on the supposition that our own lives are endangered. Now it is a fact that this very danger results, in part, from the want of habits of forbearance. We publicly profess that we would kill an assailant; and the assailant, knowing this, prepares to kill us when otherwise he would forbear.

And after all, if it were granted that a person is at liberty to take an assailant's life in order to preserve his own, how is he to know, in the majority of instances, whether his own would be taken? When a man breaks into a person's house, and this person, as soon as he comes up with the robber, takes out a pistol and shoots him, we are not to be told that this man was killed "in defence of life." Or go a step further, and a step further still, by which the intention of the robber to commit personal violence or inflict death is more and more probable:-you must at last shoot him in uncertainty whether your life was endangered or not. Besides, you can withdraw -you can fly. None but the predetermined murderer wishes to commit murder. But perhaps you exclaim-"Fly! Fly, and leave your property unprotected!" Yes-unless you mean to say that preservation of property, as well as preservation of life, makes it lawful to kill an offender. This were to adopt a new and a very different proposition; but a proposition which I suspect cannot be separated in practice from the former. He who affirms that he may kill another in order to preserve his life, and that he may endanger his life in order to protect his property, does in reality affirm that he may kill another in order to preserve his property. But such a proposition, in an unconditional form, no one surely will tolerate. The laws of the land do not admit it, nor do they even admit the right of taking another's life simply because he is attempting to take ours. They require that we should be tender even of the murderer's life, and that we should fly rather than destroy it.*

We say that the proposition that we may take life in order to preserve our property is intolerable. To preserve how much? five hundred pounds, or fifty, or ten, or a shilling, or a sixpence ? It has actually been declared that the rights of self-defence "justify a man in taking all forcible methods which are necessary, in order to procure the restitution of the freed m or the property of which he had been unjustly deprived." All forcible methods to obtain restitution of property! No limit to the nature or effects of the force! No limit to the insignificance of the amount of the property! Apply, then, the rule. A boy snatches a bunch of grapes from a fruiterer's stall. The fruiterer runs after the thief, but finds that he is too light of foot to be overtaken. Moreover, the boy eats as he runs. "All forcible methods," reasons the fruiterer, are justifiable to obtain restitution of property. I may fire after the plunderer, and when he falls regain my grapes." All this is just and right, if Gisborne's proposition is true. It is a dangerous thing to lay down maxims in morality.

66

The conclusion, then, to which we are led by these

• Blackstone: Com. v. 4, c. 4.
+ Gisborne: Moral Philosophy.

enquiries is, that he who kills another, even upon the plea of self-defence, does not do it in the predominance nor in the exercise of Christian dispositions; and if this is true, is it not also true, that his life cannot be thus taken in conformity with the Christian law?

But this is very far from concluding that no resistance may be made to aggression. We may make, and we ought to make, a great deal. It is the duty of the civil magistrate to repress the violence of one man towards another, and by consequence it is the duty of the individual, when the civil power cannot operate, to endeavour to repress it himself. I perceive no reasonable exception to the rule that whatever Christianity permits the magistrate to do in order to restrain violence, it permits the individual, under such circumstances, to do also. I know the consequences to which this rule leads in the case of the punishment of death, and of other questions. These questions will hereafter be discussed. In the mean time, it may be an act of candour to the reader to acknowledge, that our chief motive for the discussions of the present chapter, has been to pioneer the way for a satisfactory investigation of the Punishment of Death, and of other modes by which human life is taken away.

Many kinds of resistance to aggression come strictly within the fulfilment of the law of benevolence. He who, by securing, or temporarily disabling a man, prevents him from committing an act of great turpitude, is certainly his benefactor; and if he be thus reserved for justice, the benevolence is great both to him and to the public. It is an act of much kindness to a bad man to secure him for the penalties of the law or it would be such, if penal law were in the state in which it ought to be, and to which it appears to be making some approaches. It would then be very probable that the man would be reformed and this is the greatest benefit which can be conferred upon him and upon the community.

:

The exercise of Christian forbearance towards violent men is not tantamount to an invitation of outrage. Cowardice is one thing; this forbearance is another. The man of true forbearance is of all men the least cowardly. It requires courage in a greater degree and of a higher order to practise it when life is threatened, than to draw a sword or fire a pistol.

No: It is the peculiar privilege of Christian virtue to approve itself even to the bad. There is something in the nature of that calmness, and self-possession, and forbearance, that religion effects, which obtains, nay which almost commands regard and respect. How different the effect upon the violent tenants of Newgate, the hardihood of a turnkey and the mild courage of an Elizabeth Fry! Experience, incontestable experience, has proved, that the minds of few men are so depraved or desperate as to prevent them from being influenced by real Christian conduct. Let him therefore who advocates the taking the life of an agressor, first show that all other means of safety are vain; let him show that bad men, notwithstanding the exercise of true Christian forbearance, persist in their purposes of death :when he has done this he will have adduced an argument in favour of taking their lives which will not, indeed, be conclusive, but which will approach nearer to conclusiveness than any that has yet been adduced.

Of the consequences of forbearance, even in the case of personal attack, there are some examples: Archbishop Sharpe was assaulted by a footpad on the highway, who presented a pistol and demanded his money. The Archbishop spoke to the robber in the language of a fellow man and of a Christian. The man was really in distress, and the prelate gavo

G

him such money as he had, and promised that, if he would call at the palace, he would make up the amount to fifty pounds. This was the sum of which the robber had said he stood in the utmost need. The man called and received the money. About a year and a half afterwards, this man again came to the palace and brought back the same sum. He said that his circumstances had become improved, and that, through the "astonishing goodness" of the Archbishop, he had become "the most penitent, the most grateful, and happiest of his species."-Let the reader consider how different the Archbishop's feelings were, from what they would have been if, by his hand, this man had been cut off. *

Barclay, the Apologist, was attacked by a highwayman. He substituted for the ordinary modes of resistance, a calm expostulation. The felon dropped his presented pistol, and offered no further violence. A Leonard Fell was similarly attacked, and from him the robber took both his money and his horse, and then threatened to blow out his brains. Fell solemnly spoke to the man on the wickedness of his life. The robber was astonished: he had expected, perhaps, curses, or perhaps a dagger. He declared he would not keep either the horse or the money, and returned both. "If thine enemy hunger, feed him; for in so doing thou shalt heap coals of fire upon his head."t-The tenor of the short narrative that follows is somewhat different. Ellwood, who is known to the literary world as the suggester to Milton of Paradise Regained, was attending his father in his coach. Two men waylaid them in the dark and stopped the carriage. Young Ellwood got out, and on going up to the nearest, the ruffian raised a heavy club, "when," says Ellwood, "I

See Lond. Chron. Aug. 12, 1785. See also life of Granville Sharpe, Esq., p. 13.

+"Select Anecdotes, &c." by John Barclay.

[ocr errors]

whipt out my rapier and made a pass upon him. I could not have failed running him through up to the hilt," but the sudden appearance of the bright blade terrified the man so, that he stepped aside, avoided the thrust, and both he and the other fied. "At that time," proceeds Ellwood, "and for a good while after, I had no regret upon my mind for what I had done." This was whilst he was young, and when the forbearing principles of Christianity had little influence upon him. But afterwards, when this influence became powerful, "a sort of horror,” he says, "seized on me when I considered how near I had been to the staining of my hands with human blood. And whensoever afterwards I went that way, and indeed as often since as the matter has come into my remembrance, my soul has blessed Him who preserved and withheld me from shedding man's blood."*

That those over whom, as over Ellwood, the influence of Christianity is imperfect and weak, should think themselves at liberty upon such occasions to take the lives of their fellow-men, needs to be no subject of wonder. Christianity, if we would rightly estimate its obligations, must be felt in the heart. They in whose hearts it is not felt, or felt but little, cannot be expected perfectly to know what its obligations are. I know not therefore that more appropriate advice can be given to him who contends for the lawfulness of taking another man's life in order to save his own, than that he would first enquire whether the influence of religion is dominant in his mind. If it is not, let him suspend his decision until he has attained to the fulness of the stature of a Christian man. Then, as he will be of that number who do the Will of Heaven, he may hope to "know of this doctrine whether it be of God."

Ellwood's Life

ESSAY III.*

POLITICAL RIGHTS AND OBLIGATIONS.

CHAPTER I.

PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL TRUTH, AND OF POLITICAL

RECTITIUDE.

I.-"Political Power is rightly exercised only when it is possessed by consent of the community"-Governors officers of the Public-Transfer of their rights by a whole people-The people hold the sovereign power-Right of Governors-A conciliating system.

II." Political Power is rightly exercised only when it sub. serves the welfare of the community "-Interference with other nations-Present expedients for present occasionsProper business of Governments.

III. Political Power is rightly exercised only when it subserves the welfare of the community by means which the Moral Law permits"-The Moral Law alike binding on nations and individuals-Deviation from rectitude impolitic-"The Holy Alliance"-Durable fame.

THE fundamental principles which are deducible

[blocks in formation]

[This Essay the author did not live to revise, a circumstance which will account for a want of complete connexion of the different parts of a subject which the reader will sometimes meet with. There occur also in this part of the manuscript numerous memoranda, which the author intended to make use of in a future revision These are to be distinguished from the Notes, as the former refer, not to any particular passage, but only to the subject of the chapter or section. They were hastily, as the thought occurred, written in the margin or on a blank leaf of the manuscript, and they are here introduced at the bottom of the page, in those parts to which they appear to have the nearest reference.-ED.]

liberty, they are more happy than by retaining, or
attempting to retain, the whole. Government, what-
ever be its form, is the agent by which the inexpe-
dient portion of individual liberty is taken away.
Men institute government for their own advantage,
and because they find they are more happy with it
than without it. This is the sole reason, in prin-
ciple, how little soever it be adverted to in practice.
Governors, therefore, are the officers of the public,
in the proper sense of the word: not the slaves of
the public; for if they do not incline to conform to |
the public will, they are at liberty, like other officers,
to give up their office. They are servants, in the
same manner, and for the same purpose, as a solicitor
is the servant of his client, and the physician of his
patient. These are employed by the patient or the
client voluntarily for his own advantage, and for
nothing else. A nation, (not an individual, but a
nation,) is under no other obligation to obedience,
than that which arises from the conviction that obe-
dience is good for itself:-or rather, in more pro-
per language, a nation is under no obligation to obe-
dience at all. Obedience is voluntary. If they do
not think it proper to obey—that is, if they are not
satisfied with their officers-they are at liberty to
discontinue their obedience, and to appoint other
officers instead.

That which is thus true as an universal proposition, is asserted with respect to this country by the present king: *_" The powers and prerogatives of the crown are vested there as a trust for the benefit of the people; and they are sacred only as they are necessary to the preservation of that poise and balance of the constitution which experience has proved to be the best security of the liberty of the subject."+

33 66

It is incidental to the office of the First public servants, that they should exercise authority over those by whom they are selected; and hence, probably, it has happened that the terms "public officer," 'public servant," have excited such strange controversies in the world. Men have not maintained sufficient discrimination of ideas. Seeing that governors are great and authoritative, a man imagines it cannot be proper to say they are servants. Seeing that it is necessary and right that individuals should obey, he cannot entertain the notion that they are the servants of those whom they govern. The truth is, that governors are not the servants of individuals but of the community. They are the masters of individuals, the servants of the public; and if this simple distinction had been sufficiently borne in mind, much perhaps of the vehement contention upon these matters had been avoided.

But the idea of being a servant of the public, is quite consistent with the idea of exercising authority over them. The common language of a patient is founded upon similar grounds. He sends for a physician -the physician comes at his desire--is paid for his services-and then the patient says, I am ordered to adopt a regimen, I am ordered to Italy; -and he obeys, not because he may not refuse to obey if he chooses, but because he confides in the judgment of the physician, and thinks that it is more to his benefit to be guided by the physician's judgment than by his own. But it will be said the physician cannot enforce his orders upon the patient against his will neither I answer can the governor enforce his upon the public against theirs. No doubt Governors do sometimes so enforce them. What they do, however, and what they rightfully do, are separate considerations, and our business is only with the latter.

[blocks in formation]

Grotius argues that sovereign power may be possessed by governors, so that it shall not rightfully belong to the community. He says, 66 From the Jewish as well as the Roman law it appears, that any one might engage himself in private servitude to whom he pleased. Now if an individual may do so, why may not a whole people, for the benefit of better government and more certain protection, completely transfer their sovereign rights to one or more persons without reserving any portion to themselves?" * I answer, No individual may do this: and, If he might, it would not serve the doctrine in the case of nations. It never can be right for a man to resign the absolute direction of his conduct to another, because he must then do actions good or bad as that other might command-he must lie, or rob, or assassinate; and of this common sense would pronounce the impropriety, if the Moral Law did not. And if you say a man ought not so to resign himself to another, then I answer, he does not transfer sovereign power but retains it himself—which, in truth, ends the argument.

But if the doctrine were sound for the individual, it is unsound for a community. What is meant by the "transfer of their sovereign rights by a whole people?" Is every man, woman, and child, in the country formally to sign the transfer? If not, how shall a whole people transfer it? At any rate, if they did, their resignation could not bind their children or successors. Besides, there is the same objection to this transfer of the sovereign power on the part of a nation as on the part of an individual. The thing is absurd in reason, and criminal in morals.

Grotius illustrates his argument by "that authority to which a woman submits when she gives herself to her husband." But she does not submit to sovereign authority. He says again, some powers are conferred for the sake of the governor, as the right of a master over a slave." But such powers are never justly conferred.

After all, these arguments do but establish, in reality, the fundamental position. They assume that a people can resign the sovereign power; which is the same thing as to acknowledge that they rightfully possess it. Grotius himself says, "A state is a perfect body of free men, united together in order to enjoy common rights and advantages."†

It gives some anxiety to the mind of the writer, lest the reader should identify his principles with those of many who have asserted the "sovereignty of the people.' This doctrine has been insisted upon by persons who have mingled with it, or deduced from it, principles which the writer not merely rejects, but abhors. A doctrine is not unsound because it has been abvocated or perverted by bad men; and it is neither rational nor honest to reprobate a truth because it has been viciously associated. Gifford, in his life of Pitt, complains of Fox, who by

66

a strange perversion of terms, and a confusion of intellect that would have disgraced even a schoolboy, called his sovereign the servant of the people." "This," says Gifford, "was a servile imitation of the French regicides, and a direct encouragement to all the theoretical reveries of all the disaffected in England." This is the species of association which I would deprecate: French regicides taught the doctrine, and disaffected theorists taught it. I am sorry that a truth should be so connected; but it is not the less a truth. The "confusion of intellect" of which Gifford speaks, probably subsisted more in the writer than in Fox-for reasons which the reader has just seen, and because the biographer Rights of War and Peace, b. 1. c. 3, 5, 8, +Rights of War and Peace.

[ocr errors]

240972

« السابقةمتابعة »