صور الصفحة
PDF
النشر الإلكتروني

66

means of testifying the falsehood of the aspersion; | sentence above, holds much stronger language than procure their explicit and attested allegations; or, if mine. "If truth," says he, were universally told by any other means your innocence can be shown- of men's dispositions and actions, gibbets and wheels avail yourself of them, and forthwith lay your ex- might be dismissed from the face of the earth. The culpation before the public. Here the great end is knave unmasked, would be obliged to turn honest in attained. Your character is not injured; and as to his own defence. Nay, no man would have time to the slanderer, he is punished by being made the sub- grow a knave. Truth would follow him in his first ject of public reprobation and disgust. A few days irresolute essays, and public disapprobation arrest previous to that on which I write, a wide extended him in the commencement of his career.' ""* All this daily newspaper published some insinuations against is not now to be hoped: yet when men knew that the the character of a gentleman eminent in society. exposure of their misdeeds was in the uncontrollable What was done? Why, the same day or the next, power of the press, and that there were no means of a nobleman who happened to know the truth, and securing themselves from its punishment but by being whose word no one would dispute, sent a note to virtuous, would not they be more anxious to practise another paper saying, the insinuation was virtue ? Would not the dread of exposure operate founded. Was not every object then attained? upon some of the unpunished vices of private life, as Would this gentleman have been further benefited the dread of public opinion operates upon more by prosecuting the editor? or could this editor have public vices now? The restraining power of public been more appropriately punished than by this ex- opinion we know is great :-by dispensing with libel posure of his malignity? laws we should extend that power.

un

But it will be said, that there do not exist the means of disproving some aspersions, however false. This is correct; but what is to be done? If the sufferer cannot disprove it in a newspaper or pamphlet, neither can he in a court of law and unless it is disproved, a prosecution, besides procuring little or no redress, publishes the aspersion to a tenfold number. Yet such a person may demand proof of the slanderer, and require that he come forward. This, and such things, may be done in a manner that so indicates integrity and innocence, that in failure of a justification of the slander it would recoil upon the author.

The most pitiable situation is that of a person, now perhaps virtuous and good, who is charged with some of the crimes or vices of which he was actually guilty in past times. Here the libel cannot be repelled, for it is true. To invite investigation is to publish and deepen the slander. It must therefore be borne a painful alternative, but unavoidable; and he who endures it will, perhaps, if he be now a Christian, regard it with humility, as a not unjust retribution of his former sins.

But to allow the unrestrained publication of facts or falsehood, is not a matter purely evil. The statutes which prevent men from publishing libels, prevent them also from publishing truths-truths which all men ought to hear. There are some actions which can in no other way be punished or discountenanced than by exposing them to the public reprobation. I saw the other day, in a newspaper, (I think these popular references much to the purpose,) a narrative of the gross cruelty of some gentleman to his horse, by which a large part of the animal's tongue had been cut or torn from its mouth. The narrator said he was afraid to mention this man's name on account of the libel laws. Suppose the statement to have been true, and the name to have been made public; would it not have been a proper and a severe punishment for the inhumanity? Would it not have deterred others from such inhumanity? In a word, ought not such charges to be published ?—And thus it would be with a multitude of other offences, for which scarcely any punishment is so effectual as the reprobation of the public. "There is no terror that

comes home to the heart of vice, like the terror of being exhibited to the public eye." I am willing to acknowledge, that if the publication of many species of vicious conduct was more frequent-so frequent as to be habitual, it would eventually tend to the extension of private and of public virtue. Men who were in any way ill-disposed, would find themselves under a constant apprehension of exposure, from which almost no vigilance could secure an escape. The writer from whom I have quoted the

Finally, the repeal of these laws would be attended with one of two consequences. If the consequence was, that these publications were not increased in number, no evil could be done. If they were increased, and greatly increased in number, the public would soon learn to discriminate. Tales are believed now, because they are seldom told, and the public discrimination is not sufficiently habituated to distinguish the false from the true. If it were, the true only would pass current. These often ought to pass; and as to the false who would publish what no one would believe? +

Publications to the discredit of government or of its officers, assume a different character; but the difference appears to be such as still more strongly to argue against visiting them with legal penalties. Charles James Fox remarked upon this difference. He thought however that private libels, some of the true as well as the false, might rightly be punished by the state; but " in questions relating to public men," says he, "verity in respect of public measures ought to be regarded as a complete justification of a libel." Whether truth be a justification of a political libel-is one question, Whether such a libel ought to be punished by the law-is another. But I think that no statement respecting public measures ought to be punished by the law-for this simple reason amongst others :-if the statement be true, it is commonly right that the truth should be publicly known; if it be false, the mischief is better remedied by publicly showing the falsehood than by any other means. Surely to repel the aspersion upon public men, by showing that it is unfounded, is more consistent with the dignity of a government than to pursue the vituperator with fines and imprisonment. Surely this more dignified course would recommend the government and its measures to the judgments of all wise and judicious men.

ment.

To what purpose will you prosecute a true stateIf a hundred men hear of it before the prosecution, ten thousand perhaps will hear of it afterwards. Nor is this all: for I scarcely know an act which can more powerfully tend to weaken a government, than first to act amiss, and then vindictively to pursue him who mentions the misconduct. object of a government in instituting such a prose

* Godwin Enq. Pol. Just. v. 2. p. 643.

If the

+1 learn from a book which professes to give information respecting "Society and Manners in High and Low Life," that there existed (and perhaps there still exists) a House of Call in London, where he who had malice without ability might bespeak a libel upon any subject. The price was seven and sixpence. In a few hours he might hear the scandal, if such was his order, sung about the streets.-Such a fact may well affect our resolution to punish libellers by the grave power of the law.

Fell's Memoirs.

cution be to strengthen its own hands, surely it pursues the object by most inexpedient means;-and as to suppressing truth by the mere influence of terror, it is a mode of governing for which no man in this country ought to lift his voice.

A very serious point in addition is this-that almost all political libels, whether true or false, are countenanced by a party. A prosecution, therefore, however seemingly successful, is sometimes totally defeated, because the party recompenses the victim for his sufferings or his losses. The prosecution and those who conduct it become the laughing-stock of the party. In the days of Pitt, a person published a libel which that statesman declared in the House of Commons to be" the most infamous collection of sedition and treason that ever was published." "* The man was prosecuted, found guilty, and sentenced to some imprisonment. What was the result? Why, the party made a subscription for him to the amount, it was said, of four thousand pounds. What bad man would not publish a libel to be so paid? What discreet government would prosecute a libel to be so defeated?

But if the uses of a free statement of the truth be so great in the case of private persons, much more is it desirable in the case of political affairs. To discuss, and, if needful, temperately to animadvert upon the conduct of governments, is the proper business of the public. How else shall the judgment of a people be called forth and expressed? How else shall they induce an amendment in public measures? The very circumstance that government is above the customary control of the laws, is a good reason for allowing the people freely to deliver their sentiments upon its conduct. Many ill actions of the private man may be punished by the law; but how shall the ill actions of public persons be discountenanced if it be not by the expression of the public mind? A people have sometimes no other means of promoting reformations in the conduct of government, than by exposing those parts in which reformation is needed. The argument then is short.-To prosecute false political libels is unreasonable, for there are better and wiser means of procedure. To prosecute true statements is wrong, because truth ought to be freely told; and if it were not wrong, it would be absurd, because a government inflicts more injury upon itself by the prosecution than was inflicted by the statement itself.

66

As the subject maligned rises in dignity, we are presented with stronger and still stronger dissuasions to the legal prosecution of the maligner. There are more reasons against prosecuting a political than a private aspersion: there are more reasons against prosecuting aspersions upon religion than either. Supposing, which we must suppose, that religion is true, then all libels upon it must be false; and, like other false libels, are better met by proving the truth than by punishing the liar. Christianity is but ill defended," says Paley, " by refusing audience or toleration to the objections of unbelievers." + It is a scandal to religion to prosecute the man who makes objections to its truths: for what is the inference in the objector's mind but this, that we resort to force because we cannot produce arguments? Nor let me be misinterpreted if I ask, What is Christianity, or who shall define it? I may be of opinion, and in fact I am of opinion, that some of the doctrines which the professors of Christianity promulgate, are as much opposed to Christianity as some of the arguments of unbelievers. But this is not a good reason for making my judgment the standard of Truth. Yet, without a standard, how Gifford's Life. + Mor. and Pol. Phil. b. 5, c. 9.

shall we prosecute him who impugns Christianity? How, rather, shall we know whether he impugns Christianity or something else?

Truth is an overmatch for falsehood. Where they are allowed fairly to conflict, truth is sure of the victory. Who then would rob her of the victory by silencing falsehood by force? It is by such contests that the cause of truth is promoted. The assailant calls forth defenders; and it has in fact happened, that the proofs and practical authority of religion have been strengthened by defences which, but for the assaults of error, might never have been made or sought.

If it be said that fair argument, however unsound, may be tolerated, and that you only mean to punish the authors of reproachful and scandalous attacks upon religion-we answer, that these attacks, like every other, are better repelled by exposure or by neglect than by force. You can scarcely prosecute these bad men (so experience teaches) without making them cry out about persecution, and without calling around them a party who might otherwise have held their peace. They exclaim, "The sufferer believed what he wrote, and thought that to publish it was for the general good!" All this may be false, but it is specious. At any rate you cannot disprove it. Sympathy for the man induces sympathy for his principles. Another way in which a prosecution defeats its proper object is, that to prosecute a writing, whether scandalous or only false, is a sure way of making the book read. Thousands enquire for a profligate book because they hear it is of so much importance as to be prosecuted, who else would not have enquired because they would not have heard of it. So it was about forty years ago with Paine's Works. What, says gaping curiosity, can this book be, which ministers and bishops are so anxious that we should not read? Multitudes have read the profligate later works of the unhappy Lord Byron, but probably unnumbered multitudes more would have read them, if they had been prosecuted by the Attorney General and burnt by the hangman. As it is, it may be hoped they will sink into oblivion by the weight of their own obscene profaneness.*

One objection applies to nearly all prosecutions of books-that it is almost impossible to restrain the licentiousness of the press without diminishing its wholesome freedom. The boundaries of freedom and licentiousness cannot be defined by law. No law can be devised which shall at once exclude the evil and permit the good. Now to restrain the freedom of the press is amongst the greatest mischiefs which can be inflicted on mankind. The reader will be prepared to acknowledge the magnitude of the mischief, if he considers how powerful and how proper an agent public opinion is in promoting social and political reformations. There is no agent of reformation so desirable as the quiet influence of the public judgment; and, in order to make this judgment sound and powerful, the press should be free.

The general conclusion that is suggested by the present chapter, is what the intelligent and Christian reader might expect that the legislator should endeavour, so far as from time to time becomes practicable, to direct penal animadversion to those actions

This man affords an instance of that strange detraction from our own reputation with posterity to which we have before referred. He certainly wished that" dull oblivion" should not

"bar

His name from out the temple where the dead
Are honour'd by the nations."-

How preposterous, then, to be the suicide of so large a portion of his hopes, by writing what experience might teach him the nations would not honour !

which are prohibited by the Moral Law; that he should endeavour this, both by addition and deduction; by ceasing to punish that which morality does not condemn, and by extending punishment to more of those actions which it does condemn.

As to the seeming exception in the case of libels, we do not contend so much for their impunity, as that the law is not the best means of punishment. By taking the care of restraining this offence from the law and placing it in the hands of the public, the punishment would sometimes be not only more effectual but more severe.

CHAPTER XII.

OF THE PROPER ENDS OF PUNISHMENT.

The three Objects of Punishment :-Reformation of the Of fender :-Example:-Restitution-Punishment may be increased as well as diminished.

WHY is a man who commits an offence punished for the act? Is it for his own advantage, or for that of others, or for both?-For both, and primarily for his own: * which answer will perhaps the more readily recommend itself, if it can be shown that the good of others, that is, of the public, is best consulted by those systems of punishment which are most effectual in benefiting the offender himself.

When we recur to the precepts and the spirit of Christianity, we find that the one great pervading principle by which it requires us to regulate our conduct towards others, is of that operative, practical good-will-that good-will which, if they be in suffering, will prompt us to alleviate the misery, if they be vicious, will prompt us to reclaim them from vice. That the misconduct of the individual exempts us from the obligation to regard this rule, it would be futile to imagine. It is by him that the exercise of benevolence is peculiarly needed. He is the morally sick, who needs the physician; and such a physician he, who by comparison is morally whole, should be. If we adopt the spirit of the declaration, "I came not to call the righteous but sinners to repentance," we shall entertain no doubt that the reformation of offenders is the primary business of the Christian in devising punishments. There appears no reason why, in the case of public criminals, the spirit of the rule should not be acted upon-" If a brother be overtaken in a fault restore such an one." Amongst the Corinthians there was an individual who had committed a gross offence, such as is now punished by the law of England. Of this criminal Paul speaks in strong terms of reprobation in the first epistle. The effect proved to be good; and the offender having apparently become reformed, the Corinthians were directed in the second epistle, to forgive and to comfort him.

When therefore a person has committed a crime, the great duty of those who in common with himself are candidates for the mercy of God, is to endeavour to meliorate and rectify the dispositions in which his crime originates; to subdue the vehemence of his passions to raise up in his mind a power that may counteract the power of future temptation. We should feel towards these mentally diseased, as we feel towards the physical sufferer-compassion; and the great object should be to cure the disease. No

"The end of all correction is either the amendment of wicked men or to prevent the influence of ill example." This is the rule of Seneca; and by mentioning amendment first, he appears to have regarded it as the primary object.

doubt, in endeavouring this object, severe remedies must often be employed. It is just what we should expect; and the remedies will probably be severe in proportion to the inveteracy and malignity of the complaint. But still the end should never be forgotten, and I think a just estimate of our moral obligations, will lead us to regard the attainment of that end as paramount to every other.

There is one great practical advantage in directing the attention especially to this moral cure, which is this, that if it be successful, it prevents the offender from offending again. It is well known that the proportion of those who, having once suffered the stated punishment, again transgress the laws and are again convicted, is great. But to whatever extent reformation was attained, this unhappy result would be prevented.

The second object of punishment, that of example, appears to be recognised as right by Christianity, when it says that the magistrate is a "terror" to bad men; and when it admonishes such to be "afraid" of his power. There can be no reason for speaking of punishment as a terror, unless it were right to adopt such punishments as would deter. In the private discipline of the church the same idea is kept in view: "Them that sin rebuke before all, that others also may fear." ""* The parallel of physical disease may also still hold. The offender is a member of the social body; and the physician who endeavours to remove a local disease, always acts with a reference to the health of the system.

In stating reformation as the first object, we also conclude, that if, in any case, the attainment of reformation and the exhibition of example should be found to be incompatible, the former is to be preferred. I say if; for it is by no means certain that such cases will ever arise. The measures which are necessary to reformation must operate as example; and in general, since the reformation of the more hardened offenders is not to be expected, except by severe measures, the influence of terror in endeavouring reformation will increase with the malignity of the crime. This is just what we need, and what the penal legislator is so solicitous to secure. The point for the exercise of wisdom is, to attain the second object in attaining the first. A primary regard to the first object is compatible with many modifications of punishment, in order more effectually to attain the second. If there are two measures, of which both tend alike to reformation, and one tends most to operate as example, that one should unquestionably be preferred.

There is a third object which, though subordinate to the others, might perhaps still obtain greater notice from the legislator than it is wont to doRestitution or Compensation. † Since what are called criminal actions are commonly injuries committed by one man upon another, it appears to be a very obvious dictate of reason that the injury should be repaired ;-that he from whom the thief steals a purse should regain its value; that he who is injured in his person or otherwise, should receive such compensation as he may. When my house is broken into and a hundred pounds worth of property is carried off, it is but an imperfect satisfaction to me that the robber will be punished. I ought to recover the value of my property. The magistrate, in taking care of the general, should take care of the individual weal. The laws of England do now award compensation in damages for some injuries. This

[blocks in formation]
[ocr errors]

is a recognition of the principle; although it is remarkable, not only that the number of offences which are thus punished is small, but that they are frequently of a sort in which pecuniary loss has not been sustained by the injured party.

I do not imagine that in the present state of penal law, or of the administration of justice, a general regard to compensation is practicable, but this does not prove that it ought not to be regarded. If in an improved state of penal affairs, it should be found practicable to oblige offenders to recompense by their labour those who had suffered by their crime, this advantage would attend, that while it would probably involve considerable punishment, it would approve itself to the offender's mind as the demand of reason and of justice. This is no trifling consideration; for in every species of coercion and punishment, public or domestic, it is of consequence that the punished party should feel the justice and propriety of the measures which are adopted.

The writer of these Essays would be amongst the last to reprobate a strict adherence to abstract principles, as such; but some men, in their zeal for such principles, have proposed strange doctrines upon the subject of punishment. It has been said that when a crime has been committed it cannot be recalled; that it is a "past and irrevocable action," and that to inflict pain upon the criminal because he has committed it," is one of the wildest conceptions of untutored barbarism." No one perhaps would affirm that, in strictness, such a motive to punishment is right; but how, when an offence is committed, can you separate the objects of punishment so as not · practically to punish because the man has offended? If you regulate the punishment by its legitimate objects, you punish because the offender needs it; and as all offenders do need it, you punish all, which amounts in practice to nearly the same thing as punishing because they have committed a crime. However, as an abstract principle, there might be little occasion to dispute about it; but when it is made a foundation for such doctrine as the following, it is needful to recall the supreme authority of the Moral Law: "We are bound, under certain urgent circumstances, to deprive the offender of the liberty he has abused. Further than this, no circumstance can authorize us. The infliction of further evil, when his power to injure is removed, is the wild and unauthorized dictate of vengeance and rage." This is affirmative; and in turn I would affirm that it is the sober and authorized dictate of justice and good-will. But indeed why may we even restrain him? Obviously for the sake of others; and for the sake of others we may also do more. Besides, this philosophy leaves the offender's reformation out of the question. If he is so wicked that you are obliged to confine him lest he should commit violence again, he is so wicked that you are obliged to confine him for his own good. And, in reality, the writer himself had just before virtually disproved his own position. "Whatever gentleness," he says, "the intellectual physician may display, it is not to be believed that men can part with rooted habits of injustice and vice without the sensation of considerable pain. But, to occasion this pain in order to make them part with vicious habits, is to do something "further" than to take away liberty.

*

Respecting the relative utility of different modes of punishment and of prison discipline, we have little to say, partly because the practical recognition of reformation as a primary object affords good secu

Godwi: Enq. Pol. Just. v. i. p. 748, 751.

rity for the adoption of judicious measures, and partly because these topics have already obtained much of the public attention. One suggestion may, however, be made, that as good consequences have followed from making a prisoner's confinement depend for its duration on his conduct, so that if it be exemplary the period is diminished, there appears no sufficient reason why the parallel system should not be adopted of increasing the original sentence if his conduct continue vicious. There is no breach of reason or of justice in this. For the reasonable object of punishment is to attain certain ends, and if, by the original sentence, it is found that these ends are not attained, reason appears to dictate that stronger motives should be employed. It cannot surely be less reasonable to add to a culprit's penalty if his conduct be bad, than to deduct from it if it be good. For a sentence should not be considered as a propitiation of the law, nor when it is inflicted should it be considered, as of necessity, that all is done. The sentence which the law pronounces is a general rule-good perhaps as a general rule, but sometimes inadequate to its end. And the utility of retaining the power of adding to a penalty is the same in kind, and probably greater in degree, than the power of diminishing it. In one case the culprit is influenced by hope, and in the other by fear. Fear is the more powerful agent upon some men's minds, and hope upon others. And as to the justice of such an institution, it appears easily to be vindicated; for what is the standard of justice? The sentence of the law? No; for if it were, it would be unjust to abate of it as well as to add. Is it the original crime of the offender? No; for if it were, the same crime, by whatever variety of conduct it was afterwards followed, must always receive an equal penalty. The standard of justice is to be estimated by the ends for which punishments are inflicted. Now, although it would be too much to affirm that any penalty, or duration of penalty, would be just until these ends were attained, yet surely it is not unjust to endeavour their attainment by some additions to an original penalty when they cannot be attained without.

CHAPTER XIII.

PUNISHMENT OF DEATH.

Of the three objects of punishment, the punishment of death regards but one-Reformation of minor offenders: Greater criminals neglected - Capital punishments not efficient as examples-Public executions-Paul - Grotius - MurderThe punishment of death irrevocable-Rousseau-Recapitulation.

I SELECT for observation this peculiar mode of punishment on account of its peculiar importance. And here we are impressed at the outset with the consideration, that of the three great objects which have just been proposed as the proper ends of punishment, the punishment of death regards but one; and that one not the first and the greatest. The only end which is consulted in taking the life of an offender, is that of example to other men. His own reformation is put almost out of the question. Now, if the principles delivered in the preceding chapter be sound, they present at once an almost insuperable objection to the punishment of death. If reformation be the primary object, and if the punishment of death precludes attention to that object, the punishment of death is wrong.

To take the life of a fellow-creature is to exert the utmost possible power which man can possess over man. It is to perform an action the most seri

K

more efficient as examples than any others? We are not. We do not know from experience, and we cannot know without it. In England the experiment has not been made. The punishment therefore is wrong in us, whatever it might be in a more experienced people. For it is wrong unless it can be shown to be right. It is not a neutral affair. If it is not indispensably necessary, it is unwarrantable. And since we do not know that it is indispensable, it is, so far as we are concerned, unwarrantable.

ous and awful which a human being can perform. | indisputably certain that capital punishments are Respecting such an action, then, can any truth be more manifest than that the dictates of Christianity ought especially to be taken into account? If these dictates are rightly urged upon us in the minor concerns of life, can any man doubt whether they ought to influence us in the greatest? Yet what is the fact? Why, that in defending capital punishments, these dictates are almost placed out of the question. We hear a great deal about security of property and life, a great deal about the necessity of making examples; but almost nothing about the Moral Law. It might be imagined that upon this subject our religion imposed no obligations; for nearly every argument that is urged in favour of capital punishments would be as valid and as appropriate in the mouth of a Pagan as in our own. Can this be right? Is it conceivable that, in the exercise of the most tremendous agency which is in the power of man, it can be right to exclude all reference to the expressed will of God?

I acknowledge that this exclusion of the Christian law from the defences of the punishment, is to me almost a conclusive argument that the punishment is wrong. Nothing that is right can need such an exclusion; and we should not practise it if it were not for a secret perception, that to apply the pure requisitions of Christianity would not serve the purpose of the advocate. Look for a moment upon the capital offender and upon ourselves. He, a depraved and deep violator of the law of God-one who is obnoxious to the vengeance of heaven-one, however, whom Christ came peculiarly to call to repentance and to save Ourselves, his brethren-brethren by the relationship of nature brethren in some degree in offences against God-brethren especially in the trembling hope of a common salvation. How ought beings so situated to act towards one another? Ought we to kill or to amend him? Ought we, so far as is in our power, to cut off his future hope, or, so far as is in our power, to strengthen the foundation of that hope? Is it the reasonable or decent office of one candidate for the mercy of God to hang his fellow-candidate upon a gibbet? I am serious, though men of levity may laugh. If such men reject Christianity, I do not address them. If they admit its truth, let them manfully show that its principles should not thus be applied.

66

[ocr errors]

And with respect to the experience of other nations, who will affirm that crimes have been increased in consequence of the diminished frequency of executions? Who will affirm that the laws and punishments of America are not as effectual as our own? Yet they have abolished capital punishments for all private crimes except murder of the first degree. Where, then, is our pretension to a justification of our own practice? It is a satisfaction that so many facts and arguments are before the public which show the inefficacy of the punishment of death in this country; and this is one reason why they are not introduced here. "There are no practical despisers of death like those who touch, and taste, and handle death daily, by daily committing capital offences. They make a jest of death in all its forms; and all its terrors are in their mouths a scorn.' Profligate criminals, such as common thieves and highwaymen," "have always been accustomed to look upon the gibbet as a lot very likely to fall to them. When it does fail to them therefore, they consider themselves only as not quite so lucky as some of their companions, and submit to their fortune without any other uneasiness than what may arise from the fear of death--a fear which even, by such worthless wretches, we frequently see can be so easily and so very completely conquered." A man some time ago was executed for uttering forged bank-notes, and the body was delivered to his friends. What was the effect of the example upon them? Why, with the corpse lying on a bed before them, they were themselves seized in the act of again uttering forged bank notes. The testimony upon a subject like this, of a person who has had probably greater and better opportunities of ascertaining the practical efficiency of punishments than any other individual in Europe, is of great importance. Capital convicts," says Elizabeth Fry, "pacify their conscience with the dangerous and most fallacious notion, that the violent death which awaits them will serve as a full atonement for all their sins." It is their passport to felicity-the purchase-money of heaven! Of this

-66

No one disputes that the reformation of offenders is desirable, though some may not allow it to be the primary object. For the purposes of reformation we have recourse to constant oversight-to classification of offenders-to regular labour-to religious instruction. For whom? For minor crimi-deplorable notion the effect is doubly bad. First, it nals. Do not the greater criminals need refor- makes them comparatively little afraid of death, mation too? If all these endeavours are necessary because they necessarily regard it as so much less an to effect the amendment of the less depraved, are evil; and, secondly, it encourages them to go on in they not necessary to effect the amendment of the the commission of crimes, because they imagine that more? But we stop just where our exertions are the number or enormity of them, however great, most, needed; as if the reformation of a bad man will not preclude them from admission into heaven. was of the less consequence as the intensity of his Of both these mischiefs, the punishment of death is wickedness became greater. If prison discipline anda the immediate source. Substitute another punishpenitentiary be needful for sharpers and pickpockets, ment, and they will not think that that is an "atonesurely they are necessary for murderers and highway-ment for their sins," and will not receive their premen. Yet we reform the one and hang the other! sent encouragement to continue their crimes. But Since, then, so much is sacrificed to extend the with respect to example, this unexceptionable authoterror of example, we ought to be indisputably cer-rity speaks in decided language. "The terror of tain that the terror of capital punishments is greater than that of all others. We ought not certainly to sacrifice the requisitions of the Christian law unless we know that a regard to them would be attended with public evil. * Do we know this? Are we

We ought not for any reason to do this; but I speak in the present paragraph of the pretensions of expediency.

example is very generally rendered abortive by the predestinarian notion, vulgarly prevalent among thieves, that if they are to be hanged they are to be hanged, and nothing can prevent it.'" It may be said that the same notion might be attached to

[blocks in formation]
« السابقةمتابعة »