صور الصفحة
PDF
النشر الإلكتروني

The political duties which result from the Law of Nature, it is not our present business to investigate; but it may be observed here, that a very limited appeal to facts is sufficient to evince, that by many political institutions the Rights of Nature have been grievously sacrificed; and that if those Rights had been sufficiently regarded, many of these vicious institutions would never have been exhibited in the world.

[ocr errors]

It appears worth while at the conclusion of this chapter to remark, that a person when he speaks of Nature," should know distinctly what he means. The word carries with it a sort of indeterminate authority; and he who uses it amiss, may connect that authority with rules or actions which are little entitled to it. There are few senses in which the word is used, that do not refer, however obscurely, to God; and it is for that reason that the notion of authority is connected with the word. "The very

"Na

name of nature implies, that it must owe its birth to some prior agent, or, to speak properly, signifies in itself nothing." ""* Yet, unmeaning as the term is, it is one of which many persons are very fond;whether it be that their notions are really indistinct, or that some purposes are answered by referring to the obscurity of nature rather than to God. ture has decorated the earth with beauty and magnificence," -"Nature has furnished us with joints and limbs," '—are phrases sufficiently unmeaning; and yet I know not that they are likely to do any other harm than to give currency to the common fiction. But when it is said, that "Nature teaches us to adhere to truth,"-" Nature condemns us for dishonesty or deceit," --" Men are taught by nature that they are responsible beings," there is considerable danger that we have both fallacious and injurious notions of the authority which thus teaches or condemns us. Upon this subject it were well to take the advice of Boyle: " Nature," he says, "is sometimes, indeed commonly, taken for a kind of semi-deity. In this sense it is best not to use it at all." It is dangerous to induce confusion into our ideas respecting our relationship with God.

A law of nature is a very imposing phrase; and it might be supposed, from the language of some persons, that nature was an independent legislatress, who had sat and framed laws for the government of mankind. Nature is nothing: yet it would seem that men do sometimes practically imagine, that a "law of nature" possesses proper and independent authority; and it may be suspected that with some the notion is so palpable and strong, that they set up the authority of "the law of nature" without reference to the will of God, or perhaps in opposition to it. Even if notions like these float in the mind only with vapoury indistinctness, a correspondent indistinctness of moral notions is likely to ensue. Every man should make to himself the rule, never to employ the word Nature when he speaks of ultimate moral authority. A law possesses no authority; the authority rests only in the legislator: and as nature makes no laws, a law of nature involves no obligation but that which is imposed by the Divine Will.

CHAPTER III.

UTILITY.

Obligations resulting from Expediency-Limits to these obligations.

THAT in estimating our duties in life we ought to pay regard to what is useful and beneficial-to what

Milton: Christian Doct. p. 14.

Free Inquiry into the vulgarly received Notions of Nature.

is likely to promote the welfare of ourselves and of others-can need little argument to prove. Yet, if it were required, it may be easily shown that this regard to Utility is recommended or enforced in the expression of the Divine Will. That Will requires the exercise of pure and universal benevolence ;which benevolence is exercised in consulting the interests, the welfare, and the happiness of mankind. The dictates of Utility, therefore, are frequently no other than the dictates of benevolence.

Or, if we derive the obligations of Utility from considerations connected with our reason, they do not appear much less distinct. To say that to consult Utility is right, is almost the same as to say, it is right to exercise our understandings. The daily and hourly use of reason is to discover what is fit to be done; that is, what is useful and expedient: and since it is manifest that the Creator, in endowing us with the faculty, designed that we should exercise it, it is obvious that in this view also a reference to expediency is consistent with the Divine Will.

When (higher laws being silent) a man judges that of two alternatives one is dictated by greater utility, that dictate constitutes an obligation upon him to prefer it. I should not hold a landowner innocent, who knowingly persisted in adopting a bad mode of raising corn; nor should I hold the person innocent who opposed an improvement in shipbuilding, or who obstructed the formation of a turnpike road that would benefit the public. These are questions, not of prudence merely, but of morals also.

Obligations resulting from Utility possess great extent of application to political affairs. There are, indeed, some public concerns in which the Moral Law, antecedently, decides nothing. Whether a duty shall be imposed, or a charter granted, or a treaty signed, are questions which are perhaps to be determined by expediency alone: but when a public man is of the judgment that any given measure will tend to the general good, he is immoral if he opposes that measure. The immorality may indeed be made out by a somewhat different process:—such a man violates those duties of benevolence which religion imposes: he probably disregards, too, his sense of obligation; for if he be of the judgment that a given measure will tend to the general good, conscience will scarcely be silent in whispering that he ought not to oppose it.

and

It is sufficiently evident, upon the principles which have hitherto been advanced, that considerations of Utility are only so far obligatory as they are in accordance with the Moral Law. Pursuing, however, the method which has been adopted in the two last chapters, it may be observed, that this subserviency of Utility to the Divine Will, appears to be required by the written revelation. That habitual preference of futurity to the present time, which Scripture exhibits, indicates that our interests here should be held in subordination to our interests hereafter as these higher interests are to be consulted by the means which revelation prescribes, it is manifest that those means are to be pursued, whatever we may suppose to be their effects upon the present welfare of ourselves or of other men. "If in this life only we have hope in God, then are we of all men most miserable." It certainly is not, in the usual sense of the word, expedient to be most miserable. And why did they thus sacrifice expediency? Because the communicated Will of God required that course of life by which human interests were apparently sacrificed. It will be perceived that these considerations result from the truth, (too little regarded in talking of " Expediency" and " General Benevolence,") that Utility, as it respects mankind, cannot be properly consulted without taking into account our interests

in futurity. "Let us eat and drink, for to-morrow | we die," is a maxim of which all would approve if we had no concerns with another life. That which might be very expedient if death were annihilation, may be very inexpedient now.

"If ye say, We will not dwell in this land, neither obey the voice of the Lord your God, saying, No; but we will go into the land of Egypt, where we shall see no war;" "nor have hunger of bread; and there will we dwell; it shall come to pass, that the sword, which ye feared, shall overtake you there in the land of Egypt; and the famine, whereof ye were afraid, shall follow close after you in Egypt; and there ye shall die."*" We will burn incense unto the queen of heaven, and pour out drink-offerings unto her; for then had we plenty of victuals, and were well, and saw no evil. But since we left off, we have wanted all things, and have been consumed by the sword, and by the famine."-Therefore, "I will watch over them for evil, and not for good." These reasoners argued upon the principle of making expediency the paramount law; and it may be greatly doubted whether those who argue upon that principle now, have better foundation for their reasoning than those of old. Here was the prospect of advantage founded, as they thought, upon experience. One course of action had led (so they reasoned) to war and famine, and another to plenty, and health, and general well-being: yet still our Universal Lawgiver required them to disregard all these conclusions of expediency, and simply to conform to His will.

After all, the general experience is, that what is most expedient with respect to another world, is most expedient with respect to the present. There may be cases, and there have been, in which the Divine Will may require an absolute renunciation of our present interests; as the martyr who maintains his fidelity, sacrifices all possibility of advantage now. But these are unusual cases; and the experience of the contrary is so general, that the truth has been reduced to a proverb. Perhaps in nineteen cases out of twenty, he best consults his present welfare, who endeavours to secure it in another world. "By the wise contrivance of the Author of nature, virtue is upon all ordinary occasions, even with regard to this life, real wisdom, and the surest and readiest means of obtaining both safety and advantage."‡ Were it however otherwise, the truth of our principles would not be shaken. Men's happiness, and especially the happiness of good men, does not consist merely in external things. The promise of a hundred fold in this present life may still be fulfilled in mental felicity; and if it could not be, who is the man that would exclude from his computations the prospect, in the world to come, of life everlasting?

In the endeavour to produce the greatest sum of happiness, or which is the same thing, in applying the dictates of Utility to our conduct in life, there is one species of utility that is deplorably disregarded both in private and public affairs-that which respects the religious and moral welfare of mankind. If you hear a politician expatiating upon the good tendency of a measure, he tells you how greatly it will promote the interests of commerce, or how it will enrich a colony, or how it will propitiate a powerful party, or how it will injure a nation whom he dreads; but you hear probably not one word of enquiry whether it will corrupt the character of those who execute the measure, or whether it will introduce vices into the colony, or whether it will present new temptations to the virtue of the public. And yet these considerations are perhaps by far the most + Jer. xliv.

* Jer. xlii.

Dr Smith: Theo. Mor. Sent.

It is

important in the view even of enlightened expediency; for it is a desperate game to endeavour to benefit a people by means which may diminish their virtue. Even such a politician would probably assent to the unapplied proposition, "the virtue of a people is the best security for their welfare." the same in private life. You hear a parent who proposes to change his place of residence, or to engage in a new profession or pursuit, discussing the comparative conveniences of the proposed situation, the prospect of profit in the new profession, the pleasures which will result from the new pursuit ; but you hear probably not one word of enquiry whether the change of residence will deprive his family of virtuous and beneficial society which will not be replaced-whether the contemplated profession will not tempt his own virtue or diminish his usefulness--or whether his children will not be exposed to circumstances that will probably taint the purity of their minds. And yet this parent will acknowledge, in general terms, that "nothing can compensate for the loss of religious and moral character." Such persons surely make very inaccurate computations of Expediency.

As to the actual conduct of political affairs, men frequently legislate as if there was no such thing as religion or morality in the world; or as if, at any rate, religion and morality had no concern with affairs of state. I believe that a sort of shame (a false and vulgar shame no doubt) would be felt by many members of senates, in directly opposing religious or moral considerations to prospects of advantage. our own country, those who are most willing to do this receive, from vulgar persons, a name of contempt for their absurdity! How inveterate must be the impurity of a system, which teaches men to regard as ridiculous that system which only is sound!

CHAPTER IV.

THE LAW OF NATIONS. THE LAW OF HONOur.

In

Although the subjects of this chapter can scarcely be regarded as constituting rules of life, yet we are induced briefly to notice them in the present Essay, partly, on account of the importance of the affairs which they regulate, and partly, because they will afford satisfactory illustration of the principles of Morality.

SECTION I.

THE LAW OF NATIONS.

Obligations and authority of the Law of Nations-Its abuses, and the limits of its authority-Treaties.

THE Law of Nations, so far as it is founded upon the principles of morality, partakes of that authority which those principles possess; so far as it is founded merely upon the mutual conventions of states, it possesses that authority over the contracting parties which results from the rule, that men ought to abide by their engagements. The principal considerations which present themselves upon the subject, appear to be these:

1-That the Law of Nations is binding upon those states who knowingly allow themselves to be regarded as parties to it :

2 That it is wholly nugatory with respect to those states which are not parties to it:

3-That it is of no force in opposition to the Moral Law:

I. The obligation of the Law of Nations upon those who join in the convention, is plain-that is, it rests, generally, upon all civilized communities which have intercourse with one another. A tacit engagement only is, from the circumstances of the case, to be expected; and if any state did not choose to conform to the Law of Nations, it should publicly express its dissent. The Law of Nations is not wont to tighten the bonds of morality; so that probably most of its positive requisitions are enforced by the Moral Law: and this consideration should operate as an inducement to a conscientious fulfilment of these requisitions. In time of war, the Law of Nations prohibits poisoning and assassination, and it is manifestly imperative upon every state to forbear them; but whilst morality thus enforces many of the requisitions of the Law of Nations, that law frequently stops short, instead of following on to whither morality would conduct it. This distinction between assassination and some other modes of destruction that are practised in war, is not perhaps very accurately founded in considerations of morality nevertheless, since the distinction is made, let it be made, and let it by all means be regarded. Men need not add arsenic and the private dagger to those modes of human destruction which war allows. The obligation to avoid private murder is clear, even though it were shown that the obligation extends much further. Whatever be the reasonableness of the distinction, and of the rule that is founded upon it, it is perfidious to violate that rule.

So it is with those maxims of the Law of Nations which require that prisoners should not be enslaved, and that the persons of ambassadors should be respected. Not that I think the man who sat down, with only the principles of morality before him, would easily be able to show, from those principles, that the slavery was wrong whilst other things which the Law of Nations allows are right-but that, as these principles actually enforce the maxims, as the observance of them is agreed on by civilized states, and as they tend to diminish the evils of war, it is imperative on states to observe them. Incoherent and inconsistent as the Law of Nations is, when it is examined by the Moral Law, it is pleasant to contemplate the good tendency of some of its requisitions. In 1702, previous to the declaration of war by this country, a number of the anticipated 66 enemy's" ships had been seized and detained. When the declaration was made, these vessels were released, "in pursuance," as the proclamation stated, "of the Law of Nations." Some of these vessels were perhaps shortly after captured, and irrecoverably lost to their owners: yet though it might perplex the Christian moralist to show that the release was right and that the capture was right too, still he may rejoice that men conform, even in part, to the purity of virtue.

Attempts to deduce the maxims of international law as they now obtain, from principles of morality, will always be vain. Grotius seems as if he would countenance the attempt when he says, "Some writers have advanced a doctrine which can never be admitted, maintaining that the Law of Nations authorizes one power to commence hostilities against another, whose increasing greatness awakens her alarms. As a matter of expediency," says Grotius, "such a measure may be adopted; but the principles of justice can never be advanced in its favour."* Alas! if principles of justice are to decide what the Law of Nations shall authorize, it will be needful to

* Rights of War and Peace.

establish a new code to-morrow. A great part of the code arises out of the conduct of war; and the usual practices of war are so foreign to principles of justice and morality, that it is to no purpose to attempt to found the code upon them. Nevertheless, let those who refer to the Law of Nations, introduce morality by all possible means; and if they think they cannot appeal to it always, let them appeal to it where they can. If they cannot persuade themselves to avoid hostilities when some injury is committed by another nation, let them avoid them when "another nation's greatness merely awakens their alarms."

II. That the Law of Nations is wholly nugatory with respect to those states which are not parties to it, is a truth which, however sound, has been too little regarded in the conduct of civilized nations. The state whose subjects discover and take possession of an uninhabited island, is entitled by the Law of Nations quietly to possess it. And it ought quietly to possess it not that in the view of reason or of morality, the circumstance of an Englishman's first visiting the shores of a country, gives any very intelligible right to the King of England to possess it rather than any other prince, but that, such a rule having been agreed upon it, it ought to be observed; but by whom? By those who are parties to the agreement. For which reason, the discoverer possesses no sufficient claim to oppose his right to that of a people who were not parties to it. So that he who, upon pretence of discovery, should forcibly exclude from a large extent of territory a people who knew nothing of European politics, and who in the view of reason possessed an equal or a greater right, undoubtedly violates the obligations of morality. It may serve to dispel the obscurity in which habit and self-interest wrap our perceptions, to consider, that amongst the states which were nearest to the newly-discovered land, a law of nations might exist which required that such land should be equally divided amongst them. Whose law of nations ought to prevail? That of European states, or that of states in the Pacific or South Sea? How happens it that the Englishman possesses a sounder right to exclude all other nations, than surrounding nations possess to partition it amongst them?

Unhappily, our law of nations goes much further; and by a monstrous abuse of power, has acted upon the same doctrine with respect to inhabited countries; for when these have been discovered, the law of nations has talked, with perfect coolness, of setting up a standard, and thenceforth assigning the territory to the nation whose subjects set it up; as if the previous inhabitants possessed no other claim or right than the bears and wolves. It has been asked (and asked with great reason,) what we should say to a canoe-full of Indians who should discover England, and take possession of it in the name of their chief?

Civilized states appear to have acted upon the maxim, that no people possess political rights but those who are parties to the law of nations; and accordingly the history of European settlements has been, so far as the aborigines were concerned, too much a history of outrage, and treachery, and blood. Penn acted upon sounder principles: he perfectly well knew that neither an established practice, nor the Law of Nations, could impart a right to a country which was justly possessed by former inhabitants; and therefore, although Charles II. "granted" him Pennsylvania, he did not imagine that the gift of a man in London, could justify him in taking possession of a distant country without the occupiers' consent. What was 66 granted" therefore by his sovereign, he purchased of the owners; and the

sellers were satisfied with their bargain and with him. The experience of Pennsylvania has shown that integrity is politic as well as right. When nations shall possess greater expansion of knowledge, and exercise greater purity of virtue, it will be found that many of the principles which regulate international intercourse, are foolish as well as vicious; that whilst they disregard the interests of morality they sacrifice their own.

III. Respecting the third consideration, that the Law of Nations is of no force in opposition to the Moral Law, little needs to be said here. It is evident that, upon whatever foundation the Law of Nations rests, its authority is subordinate to that of the Will of God. When, therefore, we say that amongst civilized states, when an island is discovered by one state, other states are bound to refrain, it is not identical with saying that the discoverer is at liberty to keep possession by whatever means. The mode of asserting all rights is to be regulated in subordination to the Moral Law. Duplicity, and fraud, and violence, and bloodshed, may perhaps sometimes be the only means of availing ourselves of the rights which the Law of Nations grants: but it were a confused species of morality which should allow the commission of all this, because it is consistent with the Law of Nations.

tion to obey its rules. These rules are precisely upon the same footing as the laws of free-masonry, or the regulations of a reading-room. He who does not choose to subscribe to the room, or to promise conformity to masonic laws, is under no obligation to regard the rules of either.

For which reason, it is very remarkable that at the commencement of his Moral Philosophy, Dr Paley says, The rules of life "are, the Law of Honour, the Law of the Land, and the Scriptures." It were strange indeed, if that were a rule of life which every man is at liberty to disregard if he pleases; and which, in point of fact, nine persons out of ten do disregard without blame. Who would think of taxing the writer of these pages with violating a " rule of life," because he pays no attention to the Law of Honour? "The Scriptures" communicate the Will of God; "the Law of the Land" is enforced by that Will; but where is the sanction of the Law of Honour ?-It is so much the more remarkable that this law should have been thus formally proposed as a rule of life, because, in the same work, it is described as "unauthorized." How can a set of unauthorized maxims compose a rule of life? But further: the author says that the Law of Honour is a "capricious rule, which abhors deceit, Ꭹ applauds the address of a successful intrigue." And further still: "it allows of fornication, adultery, drunkenness, prodigality, duelling, and of revenge in the extreme." Surely then it cannot, with any propriety of language, be called a rule of life.

Placing, then, the obligation of the Law of Honour, as such, upon that which appears to be its proper basis-the duty to perform our lawful en

goes to a gaming-house or a race-course, and loses his money by betting or playing, he is morally bound to pay: not because morality adjusts the rules of the billiard room or the turf, not because the Law of the Land sanctions the stake, but because the party previously promised to pay it. Nor would it affect this obligation, to allege that the stake was itself both illegal and immoral. So it

A kindred remark applies to the obligation of treaties. Treaties do not oblige us to do what is morally wrong. A treaty is a string of engagements; but those engagements are no more exempt from the jurisdiction of the Moral Law, than the promise of a man to assassinate another. Does such a promise morally bind the ruffian? No: and for this reason, and for no other, that the perform-gagements-it may be concluded, that when a man ance is unlawful. And so it is with treaties. Two nations enter into a treaty of offensive and defensive alliance. Subsequently one of them engages in an unjust and profligate war. Does the treaty morally bind the other nation to abet the profligacy and injustice? No: if it did, any man might make any action lawful to himself by previously engaging to do it. No doubt such a nation and such a ruffian have done wrong; but their offence consisted in making the engagement, not in breaking it. Even if ordinary wars were defensible, treaties of offensive alliance that are unconditional with respect to time or objects, can never be justified. The state, however, which, in the pursuit of a temporary policy, has been weak enough, or vicious enough to make them, should not hesitate to refuse fulfilment, when the act of fulfilment is incompatible with the Moral Law. Such a state should decline to perform the treaty, and retire with shame-with shame, not that it has violated its engagements, but that it was ever so vicious as to make them.

SECTION 11.

THE LAW OF HONOUR.

Authority of the Law of Honour-Its character.

The Law of Honour consists of a set of maxims, written or understood, by which persons of a certain class agree to regulate, or are expected to regulate, their conduct. It is evident that the obligation of the Law of Honour, as such, results exclusively from the agreement, tacit or expressed, of the parties concerned. It binds them because they have agreed to be bound, and for no other reason. He who does not choose to be ranked amongst the subjects of the Law of Honour, is under no obliga

was; but the payment is not. The payment of

such a debt involves no breach of the Moral Law. The guilt consists not in paying the money, but in staking it. Nevertheless, there may be prior claims upon a man's property which he ought first to pay. Such are those of lawful creditors. The practice of paying debts of honour with promptitude, and of delaying the payment of other debts, argues confusion or depravity of principle. It is not honour, in any virtuous and rational sense of the word, which induces men to pay debts of honour instantly. Real honour would induce them to pay their lawful debts first and indeed it may be suspected that the motive to the prompt payment of gaming debts, is usually no other than the desire to preserve a fair name with the world. Integrity of principle has often so little to do with it, that this principle is sacrificed in order to pay them.

:

With respect to those maxims of the Law of Honour which require conduct that the Moral Law forbids, it is quite manifest that they are utterly indefensible. "If unauthorized laws of honour be allowed to create exceptions to divine prohibitions, there is an end of all morality as founded in the Will of the Deity, and the obligation of every duty may at one time or other be discharged." These observations apply to those foolish maxims of honour which relate to duelling. These maxims can never justify the individual in disregarding the obligations of morality. He who acts upon them acts wicked;

Mor. and Pol. Phil. b. iii. c. 9

unless indeed he be so little informed of the requi- The practical effects of the Law of Honour are sitions of morality, that he does not, upon this sub-probably greater and worse than we are accustomed ject, perceive the distinction between right and to suppose. Men learn, by the power of association, wrong. The man of honour therefore should pay a to imagine that that is lawful which their maxims of gambling debt, but he should not send a challenge conduct do not condemn. A set of rules which inor accept it. The one is permitted by the Moral culcates some actions that are right, and permits Law, the other is forbidden. others that are wrong, practically operates as a sanction to the wrong. The code which attaches disgrace to falsehood, but none to drunkenness or adultery, operates as a sanction to drunkenness and adultery. Does not experience verify these conclusions of reason? Is it not true that men and women of honour indulge, with the less hesitation, in some vices, in consequence of the tacit permission of the Law of Honour ? What then is to be done but to reprobate the system as a whole? In this reprobation the man of sense may unite with the man of virtue; for assuredly the system is contemptible in the view of intellect, as well as hateful in the view of purity.

Whatever advantages may result from the Law of Honour, it is, as a system, both contemptible and bad. Even its advantages are of an ambiguous kind; for although it may prompt to rectitude of conduct, that conduct is not founded upon rectitude of principle. The motive is not so good as the act. And as to many of its particular rules, both positive and negative, they are the proper subject of reprobation and abhorrence. We ought to reprobate and abhor a system which enjoins the ferocious practice of challenges and duels, and which allows many of the most flagitious and degrading vices that infest the world.

ESSAY II.

PRIVATE RIGHTS AND OBLIGATIONS.

THE division which has commonly been made of the private obligations of man, into those which respect himself, his neighbour, and his Creator, does not appear to be attended with any considerable advantages. These several obligations are indeed so involved the one with the other, that there are few personal duties which are not also in some degree relative, and there are no duties, either relative or personal, which may not be regarded as duties to God. The suicide's or the drunkard's vice injures his family or his friends: for every offence against morality is an injury to ourselves, and a violation of the duties which we owe to Him whose law is the foundation of morality. Neglecting, therefore, these minuter distinctions, we observe those only which separate the Private from the Political Obligations of Mankind.

CHAPTER I.

RELIGIOUS OBLIGATIONS.

Factitious semblances of devotion-Religious conversationSabbatical institutions-Non-sanctity of days-Of temporal employments: Travelling: Stage-coaches: "Sunday papers:" Amusements-Holydays Ceremonial institutions and devotional formularies-Utility of forms-Forms of prayer-Extempore prayer-Scepticism-Motives to Scepticism.

Or the two classes of Religious Obligations-that which respects the exercise of piety towards God, and that which respects visible testimonials of our reverence and devotion, the business of a work like. this is principally with the latter. Yet at the risk of being charged with deviating from this proper business, I would adventure a few paragraphs respecting devotion of mind.

That the worship of our Father who is in heaven consists, not in assembling with others at an appointed place and hour; not in joining in the rituals of a Christian church, or in performing ceremonies, or in participating of sacraments,* all men will agree; because all men know that these things may be done whilst the mind is wholly intent upon other affairs, and even without any believe in the existence of God, "Two attendances upon public worship is a form, complied with by thousands who never kept a Sab

* It is to be regretted that this word, of which the origin is so exceptionable, should be used to designate what are regarded as solemn acts of religion.

'bath in their lives."
""* Devotion, it is evident, is an
operation of the mind; the sincere aspiration of a
dependent and grateful being to Him who has all
power both in heaven and in earth: and as the ex-
ercise of devotion is not necessarily dependent upon
external circumstances, it may be maintained in soli-
tude or in society, in the place appropriated to worship
or in the field, in the hour of business or of quietude
and rest. Even under a less spiritual dispensation
of old, a good man "worshipped, leaning upon the
top of his staff."

Now it is to be feared that some persons, who acknowledge that devotion is a mental exercise, impose upon themselves some feclings as devotional which are wholly foreign to the worship of God. There is a sort of spurious devotion-feelings, having the resemblance of worship, but not possessing its nature, and not producing its effects. "Devotion,' says Blair, "is a powerful principle, which penetrates the soul, which purifies the affections from debasing attachments, and by a fixed and steady regard to God, subdues every sinful passion, and forms the inclinations to piety and virtue."+ To purify the affections and subdue the passions, is a serious operation: it implies a sacrifice of inclination; a subjugation of the will. This mental operation many persons are not willing to undergo and it is not therefore wonderful that some persons are willing to satisfy themselves with the exercise of a species of devotion that shall be attained at less cost.

[blocks in formation]
« السابقةمتابعة »